Hand prints in Pettakere cave, Sulawesi, Indonesia, est. 35,000 and 40,000 years old |
Wolfe too bristles at Chomsky's ad hominem attacks - "The epithets ("fraud", "liar", "charlatan") were Chomsky's way of sentencing opponents to Oblivion". But while he spends a good deal of time examining Chomky's anarchist roots and rise to fame in the anti-war movement through harsh criticisms of the Vietnam war, the real focus of the piece is Chomsky's invention, in the late 1950's, of something called Universal Grammar. UG is a theory of language in which humans, thought to essentially possess a "language organ" somewhere deep in the brain, that
"could use the "deep structure", "universal grammar" and "language acquisition device" that [the child] was born with to express what he had to say, no matter whether it came out of his mouth in English, Urdu or Nagamese."Regular readers of this blog will note that I am a Board Certified Behavior Analyst. In my practice I work with children with developmental disabilities (primarily autism), who suffer severe language deficits. As such, I am trained in the science of behavior, the philosophy of which is called Radical Behaviorism. From Wikipedia:
Radical behaviorism differs from other forms of behaviorism* in that it treats everything we do as behavior, including private events such as thinking and feeling. Unlike John B. Watson's behaviorism, private events are not dismissed as "epiphenomena," but are seen as subject to the same principles of learning and modification as have been discovered to exist for overt behavior. Although private events are not publicly observable behaviors, radical behaviorism accepts that we are each observers of our own private behavior.(*these other forms are largely no longer practiced, radical behaviorism today being the predominant philosophy at the root of applied behavior analysis, experimental analysis of behavior, organizational behavioral management and relational frame theory)
As a behavior analyst, I am not an expert in language per say. I'm certainly not trained in linguistics, nor speech pathology. That said, as much as language is behavior, I understand how it works quite well. Behaviorism as a field draws much of its foundation from the work of B.F. Skinner. More than anyone else, he developed and expanded upon the notions of reinforcement and punishment, antecedents and consequences, discriminative stimuli, motivating operations and schedules of reinforcement to establish a robust theory of language. In 1957, he too published a landmark book, Verbal Behavior. Again, from Wikipedia:
For Skinner, the proper object of study is behavior itself, analyzed without reference to hypothetical (mental) structures, but rather with reference to the functional relationships of the behavior in the environment in which it occurs.Within Behaviorism, Chomsky is famous for his harsh criticism of Verbal Behavior, in which he generally misunderstands its fundamental concepts and levels baseless attacks. Outside Behaviorism, however, Chomsky is famous for utterly refuting Skinner, igniting the "Cognitive Revolution", and generally assigning Behaviorism to the dustbin of history. Behaviorists are endlessly baffled by a dismissal of Verbal Behavior that continues to this day, as psychology, education and language students are routinely taught Skinner only in passing, and with nowhere near the depth required to truly understand his work.
I must pause. I realize that sounds like a suspicious plea. Oh, if only they understood our work, they would agree with it. The implication is, well, kind of Chomskian in its dismissal of disagreement: your objections are not valid because you haven't taken the time to understand the subject. Maybe you have become too accustomed to the decadence of your bourgeois hegemony, non, comrade?
To start with, behaviorism is actually quite hard. For starters, it is deterministic, and thus in opposition to traditionally dominant notions of free will and agency that are the very pillars of entire religious and political dogmas. It is also highly technical and reliant on an elaborate network of scientific principles that much each be understood in their own right before the larger whole is assembled into a coherent theory. And finally, it is often quite unintuitive. Aside from its refutation of free will (an assertion many will reject outright based on what will be described as self-evidence), it's principles describe interactions between events that take place across a timeline that isn't easily grasped at first. In this way it is like the theory of evolution, which requires a pulling-together of a number of various concepts (mutation, natural selection, change over time), and that can't be pointed to easily as a process unfolding right before our eyes.
In another piece I've been working on, I plan to go into more detail as to what I think Chomsky's motivations, or possibly as important, the larger public embrace of his supposed refutation of behaviorism's explanation of language. I hope to have that up soon. But as one might imagine, Verbal Behavior and Chomsky's notion of a Universal Grammar were bound to conflict. Now, contrary to common understanding, behaviorism does not believe in the tabula rasa view of humans, in which we are entirely a product of our environment. Rather, behaviorism understands that every organism has certain genetic proclivities for certain stimuli - these drive our basic wants and needs (food, sex, shelter, touch, etc.). And within our species there are no doubt a range of individual differences in proclivity - some people will be more sensitive to certain stimuli more than others.
However, this is only the beginning. We are learning creatures, and possess a basic tendency to behave in certain ways more or less, depending on physiological desires and the ways in which the environment does or does not stimulate them. In this way, we are no different than most (if not all) other mammals. If a baby chick makes a certain sound near her mother, and is rewarded by more attention, she will be more likely to make that sound again when her mother is near. If a dolphin eats a certain type of fish and is disgusted by the taste, it will be less likely to eat that fish again. If a bear hears the sound of a car and follows it to a campground filled with tasty potato chips, it will be more likely to follow that sound again (however, if following the sound is followed by no chips - or worse, a gunshot - it will be less likely).
When we drive past a sign in a store window announcing "75% OFF ALL ITEMS"*, we will be more likely to go into the store. Of course, as humans, our behaviors will be somewhat more complex. We will be likely, in fact, to begin a behavioral chain that we have learned (that has been REINFORCED, or has been previously followed by benefits): for starters, the words of the sign have previously been reinforced ("75% off" = wow!, VERY available; all items"). Seeing that the store is one in which many items you enjoy are found within, you become extra excited. You then engage in the behavior of thinking about what you might want there. When you realize you could really use an antique Buddha lamp you've been eyeing in the window (a behavior previously reinforced by a college course you took in which you discovered the Buddha and how he reminded you (conditioning) of Santa Claus, whose appearance was consistently followed by presents), you are even more likely to pull over. You now engage in a series of responses - checking your mirror, turning on the signal, turning the wheel - all of which you have learned have the desired effect of safely navigating the car where you want it to go (previously engaging in that behavior has had precisely the same result).
(*In fact, just reading "75% off" likely evoked in you a bit of conditioned warm feelings as you have likely been conditioned by our society to respond to large discounts).
Have you ever walked into a room and realized you forgot why you went there in the first place? Have you ever been reading a book and realized that you hadn't even noticed the last couple of paragraphs you were reading because your mind was elsewhere? These seem strange because they are unexpected moments in which "mindless" behavior is obvious. But in reality, how much of our daily behavior is indeed "mindless" anyway? In behaviorism, this "mindlessness" is easily explained in behavioral terms, as a part of our normal conditioning. In fact, even our awareness of our actions is the product of conditioning; the language we use to describe it is Verbal Behavior. The "radical" in Radical Behaviorism emphasizes this completeness: it deals not only with observable behavior, but with the verbal behavior that takes places within our own minds as well.
So what to make of Chomsky's Universal grammar? It isn't necessarily inconsistent with behaviorism. One could imagine the human brain possessing some structure that finds certain patterns of stimulus more reinforcing. We do seem to see this in universal preferences for certain symmetrical facial features, or compositional patterns in art. However, the real issue is more philosophical, and has to do with emphasis. Is language something that is created by a physiological structure in the brain - a sort of computational device, or is it something that emerges over time, out of repeated interactions between the brain and the environment?
Chomsky preferred the former. While he couldn't point to any such structure yet discovered, he assumed it was only a matter of time before it would be. Mainly, he argued, the fact that humans were capable of generating utterly new thoughts and ideas refuted the notion that we were bound by our experiential interactions with the world. He pointed out that small children were able quickly to imagine and speak of things which they had no direct knowledge. He noted as well that all human languages had certain patterns in common. This was clear evidence that there was something universal about language, something that had evolved in our species.
Wolfe describes how influential Chomsky's position became. Despite a lingering lack of evidence for any organic grammar structure, his theory was massively popular, and helped propel linguistics as a field into increasing popularity.
"Thanks to Chomsky's success, linguistics rose from being merely a satellite orbiting around language studies and became the main event on the cutting edge... the number of full, formed departments of linguistics soared."The so-called "cognitive revolution" ushered in an era in which the context of the speaker (history, stimuli, motivations, etc.) was less important than the structures presumed to exist within the brain. Although, still without much evidence of what or where those structures were in the brain, researchers had to be content with inventing metaphors for these supposed mental processes. Chomsky's emphasis on physical structure inspired elaborate conceptualizations that were themselves rooted in 3D dimensional intuitions: sorting, shifting, stacking, storing, building, etc. With the rise of the computer, which was indeed a physical system in which code could be written and organized that did all these things, a perfect analogy was there for the taking. What was the mind, it could intuitively be imagined, but a computer of flesh and blood?
But we had made this mistake before. Rene Descartes, writing in 1647, reasoned that the mind could not be part of the body because it was ethereal and indivisible, as the body was corporeal and thus divisible.
[T]here is a great difference between the mind and the body, inasmuch as the body is by its very nature always divisible, while the mind is utterly indivisible. For when I consider the mind, or myself in so far as I am merely a thinking thing, I am unable to distinguish any parts within myself; I understand myself to be something quite single and complete….By contrast, there is no corporeal or extended thing that I can think of which in my thought I cannot easily divide into parts; and this very fact makes me understand that it is divisible. This one argument would be enough to show me that the mind is completely different from the body….The notion of the "mind" being an entity separate from causality, and therefore from the body, is known as Cartesian Dualism, and is a fallacy. As Daniel Dennet writes in Consciousness Explained:
Cartesian materialism is the view that there is a crucial finish line or boundary somewhere in the brain, marking a place where the order of arrival equals the order of "presentation" in experience because what happens there is what you are conscious of. [...] Many theorists would insist that they have explicitly rejected such an obviously bad idea. But [...] the persuasive imagery of the Cartesian Theater keeps coming back to haunt us—laypeople and scientists alike—even after its ghostly dualism has been denounced and exorcised.
Somehow, however, the dualist trappings of cognitivism persisted. While behaviorism explicitly opposes it as mentalistic, and by definition non-deterministic and unscientific, the idea "that the mind and mental states exist as causally efficacious inner states of persons" has been a major assumption of many cognitive theories for the last half-century.
Wolfe fast-forwards us to 2005. A paper by Linguist Daniel L. Everett, titled Cultural Constraints on Grammar and Cognition, described a tiny Amazonian tribe, the Pirahã , who Everett had spent a great deal of time with as a Christian missionary, and whose language broke all the Chomskian rules of Universal Grammar. Indeed, it was observed that it was the culture of the Pirahã themselves that defined their language.
"...Their unique ways of living shaped the language - not any "language organ", not any "universal grammar" or "deep structure" or "language acquisition device" that Chomsky said all languages had in common.This was a people who lived radically different lives than most everyone else on the planet. Intensely isolated, they lived in a world most of us wouldn't recognize. Because of their cultural patterns, they simply had no use for concepts and ideas most of us might take for granted. They used almost no tools, they kept few material goods, neither read nor wrote, and had no mathematical concepts beyond "a lot" and "a little". When Everett showed them black and white images, they struggled to make sense of them, so unaccustomed as they were to pattern recognition. Furthermore, they had no words for yesterday, or tomorrow, but rather referred to them as "other days". With little conception of the past, Everett's attempts at converting them to the Christian faith were hopeless. In a hilarious (and honestly, quite triumphant, personally) passage of the article, Wolfe writes of what happened when Everett tried to teach them about Jesus:
"How tall is he?" the Pirahã would ask.To a behaviorist, this makes perfect sense. Culture evolves, and with it language. Why would a language develop if it wasn't being reinforced? To the Pirahã , who had no use for concepts of tomorrow or yesterday, no such language was needed. The universal structures Chomsky proposed to have evolved in all humans were curiously absent in in the Pirahã. Everett argued that this was, as the New Scientist described his claim, "the final nail in the coffin for Chomsky's hugely influential theory of universal grammar... [that] most linguists still hold to its central idea."
"Well, I really don't know, but -"
"Does he have hair like you?" meaning red hair.
"I don't know what his hair was like, but -"
The Pirahã lost interest in Jesus immediately.... After about a week.... one of the Pirahã, [named] Kohoi, said to Everett politely but firmly, "We like you Dan, but don't tell us any more about Jesus."
In my work, I regularly encounter children who completely lack any language, or as we say - a verbal behavior repertoire. There can be many reasons for this, but often, the most salient reason is lack of learning opportunities. What this generally means is that, either because of their genetic make-up or specific environmental history, they require more exposure to certain stimuli before relationships develop. We apply the principles developed by Skinner in Verbal Behavior, in which different contingencies of reinforcement are targeted for different language skills. We teach echoic (vocal) imitation to begin to develop in the learner the ability to produce certain sounds. We find motivating items and make their availability contingent on emitting certain requesting ("manding") behavior, usually either by handing a correct image of the item, or signing or making a correct vocalization. We teach receptive language skills by saying the name of an item or activity and reinforcing when the child indicates the correct response. We teach labeling by asking what an item is and reinforcing the correct response. We teach what Skinner called "intraverbal" behavior, in which a response is controlled only by other verbal behavior, i.e. not simply what is in the room (e.g. What do you wear on your head? Hat). We teach matching and categorizing items into groups by what features they share, what they do, or logical classification.
All of these skills are slowly built up in a child until the skills, as a whole, represent a language repertoire. The child is now talking. The child is now thinking. Now, by definition, these children have a disability. They were not raised in an environment completely lacking in language. For whatever reason, they were not able to "pick up" language as easily as their typical peers. There are many reasons for this, and much is still not yet understood. However, a common feature of the autism diagnosis is that what is sensorially pleasing to a typical child might not be so to a child with autism. For instance, eye contact, a critical component of social connection, is often lacking in autistic children.
And yet it is critical for learning. When a baby makes eye contact with you and you smile back, indicating joy, the baby experiences social reinforcement. This will go on to become one of the most powerful mechanisms in the child's life as it grows and begins interacting with the world. Some of the first behaviors of an infant are shaped by differential social reinforcement. That is, when a baby says "mago mago", we likely show little excitement, and there is little reward for the child. It will be no more likely to occur again. However, if the child says "mama mama", and our eyes light up and our cheeks rise and the corners of our mouth widen, that behavior has just been rewarded, and will be more likely to occur again. The baby wants that response, and so will say mama over and over. Soon, it realizes that when it says "mama", we stop what we are doing and pay it attention. That little word is like a giant invisible rope that it can now use to turn us around. Yet, if the child is uninterested in your facial expressions, it will miss the difference in response you show. It won't be able to learn to say words that can use to control its environment.
This process of conditioning extends its reach into every aspect of our lives. More words mean more leverage in the world. They mean more access to new items and activities. They mean more thoughts and ideas. Children without language live in very simple worlds, with only the simplest access to rudimentary, basic sensory activities. But as language develops, so to does their world: a toy car is no longer a thing with wheels that spin, it is a people mover that drives on a road and crashes into things! Little people panic and move out of the way. Categories of community helpers need to come and help put out the fire. Friendships are forged in trust over the terrible disaster. Social relationships are explored and complex emotions are developed.
Nature versus nurture has always been a puzzle. As soon as babies are born - even within the womb, really, they begin to experience environmental stimuli and the process of conditioning. What would it be like if a child was raised without humans around? We've never been able to do such an experiment, for obvious ethical reasons. However, in these children, who lack a typical means of conditioning, you in some ways have a control group for what it would look like. It is as if they weren't exposed to the normal contingencies that day to day social life exposes typical children to. Like the Pirahã people, they are cut off from that process of socialization, even if unlike the Pirahã, the barrier is not geographic, but physiological.
Apparently Chomsky wasn't moved in the slightest by Everett's revelations. Wolfe writes that Chomsky told him Everett's opinion "amounts to absolutely nothing, which is why linguists pay no attention to it." A reaction strikingly similar to the one he gave Skinner in 1957. At least then he wrote a scathing review. The original idea, which assumed some mysterious physiological organ capable of generating new thought independent of one's environmental context, which threw out the notion of language as a behavior conditioned for like any other, which revolutionized the fields of psychology, linguistics and education among others, was finally refuted by a small tribe in Brazil. Meanwhile Behaviorism, the field which Skinner was instrumental in developing, and for whose work he received the Humanist of the Year Award in 1972, which spawned multiple journals and is today the pre-eminent treatment for Autism and has helped millions of individuals begin to speak, still struggles to find mainstream acceptance.
Wolfe closes by noting that despite Chomsky's theory failing to ever find any hard evidence, he
"had made the most ambitious attempt since Aristotle's in 350B.C. to explain what language exactly is. And no one else in human history had come even close. It was dazzling in its own flailing way..."
Actually, nothing could be further from the truth. Behaviorists have not only a much better explanation, but we put it into practice on a daily basis. While it may be a rather complex, a bit unintuitive, and downright subversive to many traditional ways of thinking, its results are indeed quite dazzling. To those of us in the field, we can hardly keep from imagining how transformative a larger, more widespread adoption of our techniques and principles might be in other areas of human development, such as education, or criminal justice. And something tells me, the foundation of our science is a lot more solid than might be overturned by researching an obscure population in a remote part of the world. As I used to tell my students when I taught high school biology, all it would take to overturn evolutionary theory would be to find fossilized remains of a human in a strata of rock from the age of the dinosaurs, so too might we find an ancient culture whose language was not explainable by conditioning or reinforcement. But I won't hold my breath.
No comments:
Post a Comment