But while I find that thesis boring, I found what he mentioned in passing, the discussion of free will with relation to moral responsibility, an important issue to parse.
Since the time of Laplace, the idea that a law-governed universe must also be a deterministic universe has become a fairly common assumption; and as a result, free will and all that depends upon it have often fallen into doubt and disrepute. And chief among the things that seem to depend upon free will is the possibility of moral responsibility. It seems misguided, perhaps even nonsensical, to praise or blame people for doing things they could not help doing. And some have argued, in a similar vein, that one cannot have a duty to do something unless one is actually capable of doing it: in the words of Laplace's German contemporary, the philosopher Immanuel Kant, "'ought' implies 'can'". If this is correct - if ethical notions like duty and responsibility make sense only if there is free will - then determinism would imply that all such ethical talk is literally nonsense.
Destruction of moral responsibility is often the primary
issue defenders of libertarian free will have with determinism; they fear that
without it, society would crumble. If one is not accountable for their actions –
either to be praised or blamed, then what basis do we have for a cooperative
society of laws? However, moral
responsibility is different than moral accountability. While it may be true that no one is truly
responsible for their actions, we can certainly make sure that they are
accountable to the extent that we determine is fair.
The idea of people acting with no sense of moral
responsibility is an understandable fear.
But its answer I think is found in the resolution of an even deeper
problem: if I am fully caused, and neither to be praised or blamed, what is the
purpose of my existence; what sense is there in doing anything, either good or
evil?
The bad news is that there is no ultimate sense in doing
either. The good news is that one has no
choice. Any choice one makes will have
been caused. So for those who think that
the end of personal responsibility means the granting of freedom to do whatever
one wishes, the reasons for doing so remain the same. Refusing to go to work still means one will
get fired and end up penniless. Stealing
from a neighbor will still cause them to suffer. Climbing Mt. Everest will still fill one with
the sense of awe and sense of accomplishment.
Being kind and loving to one’s family will fill them with joy.
So while none of these acts may have special cosmic significance,
we can take comfort in the fact that we are in the end, simple human creatures,
evolved to take certain pleasures in our worldly endeavors. We might curse the limitation of our
corporeal forms, but somewhat paradoxically, that curse itself is merely a
product of circumstance; it too is fully caused.
But let us take a deeper look at causation, specifically
that of morality. The fear of the
destruction of moral responsibility is a social claim. That is, it has to do with the interaction of
individuals within society. The moral
responsibility of a man on a desert island is irrelevant. It is only when he comes into contact with
others that moral claims begin. His
responsibilities lie in the dynamics of his relationship to others. He has feelings towards them, and they him, regarding
the effects of their respective actions.
Moral responsibility is compatible with determinism if we
think of it in this macro, societal sense, and place it within a utilitarian
framework. That is, we can say no one is
himself responsible, but rather the norms and values society has designed for
them to live by, which have emerged from the wisdom of history, define his
responsibility.
Through the centuries and millennia, humans have evolved
complex cultural and philosophical norms so as to structure our societies with
no greater aim than to maximize individual and group harmony. Of course there have been great failures, and
nothing like complete success has ever been achieved. Each of us play our small part, and – like Adam
Smith’s invisible hand – the group project steadily emerges. All of it terrifically complex in largely
incomprehensible, one man can neither understand all of it not affect all of
it. In this way, it is like the
individual: terrifically complex, he neither understands himself entirely, nor
affects the entirety of his own choices.
And just as society cannot be said to have free will, that is to say it
is determined by and emerges from its antecedent participants (philosophers,
politicians, journalists, public, etc.), so too is the individual determined by
and emergent from his antecedent causes (thoughts, feelings, impulses, etc.).
And just as a society cannot choose to be anything other
than what it is at any given moment, neither can man. If a fascist dictator
comes to power, it will be because of specific historical and cultural
circumstance. Sure, an alternative course
would have been preferable, but alas, it was not to be. Thankfully, our human capacity of reflection
provides some ability to learn from our mistakes. This cognitive power is the mechanism by
which humanity slowly provides itself an opportunity for moral responsibility,
or, what might be better described as moral accountability. Interaction on a global scale, over decades
and centuries, we have the opportunity to right historical wrongs, thus holding
ourselves accountable for what we hope will be a system of laws and political
structures more conducive to what we perceive as having been lacking in the
past.
So too, if no individual is truly morally responsible for
his acts, himself a conglomeration of antecedent impulses, he will be held
accountable for his actions to the extent that they interact with his fellow
man. Because of power dynamics, he may
be more or less accountable (the dictator, for instance, or powerful boss,
might have few around to hold him to sufficient account for what they feel he
has done). And here, social institutions
provide the direct framework within which power dynamics are established. Aside from whatever the individual’s personal
sense of moral responsibility to his fellow man might be, his fellow man will
have an opportunity to hold him accountable according to the structures that
have been established in the society within which they interact.
When wildfires rage, they often do great damage to homes. Of course, we do not for a second think that a
lick of flame is morally responsible.
Yet neither do we allow the fires to rage unchecked. We put them out as best we can. We also take preventative measures, so as to
reduce the possibility that wildfires will rage to begin with. We do the same with our children. Whether we see in them moral responsibility
or not, we teach them to be caring, thoughtful and kind, hopefully so that they
will grow up to be positive, productive members of society. When they err, we hold them accountable, regardless
of how they felt about their actions.
Some of us might feel the need to sate an appetite for revenge, and
include that satiation in their desire for accountability. But in the end, all that matters is that they
be held accountable. We want their
actions to have consequences, regardless of what may or may not be in their
heads, unless it might have bearing on the degree to which we feel they might
act in the future, at which point its bearing only enters with regard to a more
clear picture of accountability.
No comments:
Post a Comment